they are
satisfactory. But the moviegoer expects to see actions and the chain of
reactions
they set off
rather than exclusively to be told about them.
As Francis
Fergusson points out, all dramatic action is primarily that of the psyche or
soul. This is
what novels and plays share with film. Although the stories in film genres
like the western
and the thriller are, of course, less exalted than the work of Sophocles,
simple quest
stories often involve the action and reaction of the psyche. The western hero
avenging his
father's death or Sam Spade (Humphrey Bogart) in John Huston's The
Maltese
Falcon (194I) seeking his partner's murderer advances through
suspense-making
physical and
moral adventures toward a confrontation and a denouement. The episodes
through which he
proceeds cannot be reversed, as in episodic plots, which lack causality;
once Sam Spade
learns of the murder of his partner and announces that a detective whose
partner's murder
is unsolved is allowing something that is "bad for business," he cannot
be deterred from
his work in spite of "the Fat Man" (Sidney Greenstreet), Peter Loire,
Elisha Cook,
Jr., or Mary Astor; he may seem to become interested in the money and the
adventuress, but
his purpose goes by the most direct route to its fulfillment. As in
Oedipus Rex, the
plot in The Maltese Falcon follows a causal sequence during which a
series of
probable events leads to the confrontation of all the possible murderers and to
the denouement,
at which Mary Astor, rejected by Bogart, rides down the elevator in
police custody,
the bars of the sliding elevator door casting shadows on her face, as if she
were already in
prison,
Probability
within a causal sequence remains the chief feature of any good plot. The
organic nature
of continuity requires that probability--the necessity that what is most
likely to happen
in given circumstances, rather than what is freakishly possible, should
happen--be
maintained throughout a film. Foreshadowing is both a fictional and a
cinematic device
that elevates the merely possible to the probable. Because it is now a
historical fact,
the assassination of President Kennedy is of course "possible," but from
the point of
view of art it is "improbable." When Bruce Conner gives the event a
continuity he
gives it probability.
In order for an
event to be probable in art, the audience requires knowledge, or hints,
of antecedent
actions and motivations of character. For example in Carol Reed's The
Third Man
(1949), pictures of a cat licking a boot in a doorway prepare the moviegoer for
the knowledge
that Harry Lime (Orson Welles) is alive, Without such preparation, the
"resurrection"
of Lime would be improbable. In Citizen Kane (1941), which turns on the
question, "Who
is 'Rosebud'?"--Kane's last word--the meaning is subtly planted before
the probable
denouement. The snow scene in the glass ball that the dying Kane drops
after he utters
the name "Rosebud" is followed in a later sequence by an actual snow
scene in which
the boy Kane is playing with his sled. When the boy, who is reluctant to
leave with
Thatcher, hits the older man in the stomach with the sled, the viewer glimpses
the trade-mark
of a rosebud on the sled, (Orson Welles, as director, is careful, however,
not to reveal
the written word Rosebud, which is also on the sled, until the end of the
film.) As the
boy leaves his farm, a long, detailed shot shows the sled piling up with
snow, its trade
mark and name again hidden. As the boy later unwraps a Christmas
present, he
rejects the gift of a sled—it is not Rosebud. These visual clues, known
fully
only in
retrospect, make the film's continuity probable. At the end of the film, the
sled
with the name
Rosebud burns among the effects left behind by Kane, signaling the detour
in Kane's life
that has taken him from his mother s boarding house, where he might have